Christian Principles and War

Category:
Kingdom of Peace
Kingdom of Peace
Name:
Jonathan Dymond
Times:
1796–1828
Famous in:
Philosophy
Non-Violence
Religion:
Protestant Christianity
School:
Quaker
Teaching:
Non-Violence
War is against Christian Principles
Works Online:
Christian Principles and War

An Inquiry
Into The Accordance Of War
With the Principles Of Christianity
And
An Examination Of The Philosophical Reasoning
By Which It Is Defended
With Observations On Some Of The Causes Of War
And On Some Of Its Effects


by JONATHAN DYMOND (1796–1828)


Contempt, prior to examination, however comfortable to the mind which entertains it, or however natural to great parts, is extremely dangerous; and more apt than almost any other disposition, to produce erroneous judgments both of persons and opinions.” – Paley


Index

A. PREFACE

B. TRANSCRIBER’S NOTES

1. Causes of War | CHAPTER 1

2. Inquiry: Christianity and War | CHAPTER 2

3. The Effects of War | CHAPTER 3


PREFACE

The object of the following pages is to give a view of the principal arguments that maintain the indefensibility and impolicy of war, and to examine the reasoning that is advanced in its favour.

The author has not found, either in those works that treat exclusively of war, or in those that refer to it as part of a general system, any examination of the question that embraced it in all its bearings.

In these pages, therefore, he has attempted, not only to inquire into its accordance with Christian principles, and to enforce the obligation of these principles,

but to discuss those objections to the advocate of peace which are advanced by philosophy, and to examine into the authority of those which are enforced by the power of habit and by popular opinion.

Perhaps no other apology is necessary for the intrusion of this essay upon the public, than that its subject is, in a very high degree, important.

Upon such a subject as the slaughter of mankind, if there is a doubt, however indeterminate, whether Christianity does not prohibit it –

if there is a possibility, however remote, that the happiness and security of a nation can be maintained without it, an examination of such possibility or doubt may reasonably obtain our attention.

The advocate of peace is, however, not obliged to avail himself of such considerations –

at least, if the author had not believed that much more than doubt and possibility can be advanced in support of his opinions, this inquiry would not have been offered to the public.

He is far from amusing himself with the expectation of a general assent to the truth of his conclusions. Some will probably dispute the rectitude of the principles of decision, and some will dissent from the legitimacy of their application.

Nevertheless, he believes that the number of those whose opinions will accord with his own is increasing, and will yet much more increase;

and this belief is sufficiently confident to induce him to publish an essay which will probably be the subject of contempt to some men, and of ridicule to others. But ridicule and contempt are not potent reasons.

Christianity can only operate as an alternative:

By the mild diffusion of its light and influence, the minds of men are insensibly prepared to perceive and correct the enormities which folly, or wickedness, or accident have introduced into their public establishments.

It is in the hope of contributing, in a degree however unimportant or remote, to the diffusion of this light and influence that the following pages have been written.

For the principles of this little volume, or for its conclusions, no one is responsible but the writer: they are unconnected with any society, benevolent or religious.

He has not written it for a present occasion, or with any view to the present political state of Europe. A question like this does not concern itself with the quarrels of the day.

It will perhaps be thought by some readers that there is contained, in the following pages, greater severity of animadversion than becomes an advocate of peace.

But, “let it be remembered that to bestow good names on bad things is to give them a passport in the world under a delusive disguise.

The writer believes that wars are often supported because the system itself and the actions of its agents are veiled in glittering fictions.

He has therefore attempted to exhibit the nature of these fictions and of that which they conceal; and to state, freely and honestly, both what they are not, and what they are.

In this attempt it has been difficult – perhaps it has not been possible – to avoid some appearance of severity, but he would beg the reader always to bear in his recollection that if he speaks with censure of any class of men, he speaks of them only as a class.

He is far from giving to such censure an individual application. Such an application would be an outrage of all candour and all justice.

If again he speaks of war as criminal, he does not attach guilt, necessarily, to the profession of arms:

He can suppose that many who engage in the dreadful work of human destruction may do it without a consciousness of impropriety, or with a belief of its virtue.

But truth itself is unalterable:

whatever is our conduct, and whatever our opinions, and whether we perceive its principles or not, those principles are immutable;

and the illustration of truth, so far as he has the power of discovering it, is the object of the inquiry which he now offers to the public.

TRANSCRIBER’S NOTES

The first edition of Dymond’s Inquiry into the Accordance of War with the Principles of Christianity, also simply and understandably known as On War, was published in 1823.

It was doubtlessly both the product and the inspiration of the peace and non-resistance societies that were springing up in the early 19th century.

Leo Tolstoy highly praised it in his Kingdom of God is Within You, and I can appreciate why:

In it, Dymond addresses the psychology of those who support war and systematically dissects and rebuts their arguments.

The profession of soldiering has become a little more civilized in the last two centuries, if such a thing were possible (and I do mean only a little),

so that Dymond’s evaluation of the pervasive corruption, ignorance, indolence, and immorality of the military is now too severe.

He does, however, raise many points that are still quite valid:

I dare to say that the patriotism of many would wane if the military only provided room and board with no other pay or benefits. Who will deny that military bases are magnets for prostitution?

Once taught to kill, soldiers must then decide whom to kill, and too many innocent civilians still die due to tragic mistakes and fits of rage. (They are now euphemistically referred to a collateral damage.)

A soldier is still not permitted to leave the military before the term of his service has expired, the term of his service may be unilaterally extended by the government when it is expedient to do so, and orders are to be obeyed without question to support military discipline – hence Dymond’s charges of despotism and near slavery.

Conscription is the norm in many countries, and may well be the law again in America. The treatment of those who refuse to fight is not quite so brutal any more, but they are punished nonetheless.

Dymond describes the torture of soldiers that was prevalent in his day and, although that practice is no longer prevalent (at least toward our own soldiers), the place from which the present day’s practices have evolved should give us pause.